Beyond Stevens:
A revised approach to measurement
for geographic information

Presented at AUTO-CARTO 12
Charlotte, North Carolina; March 1995
by Nicholas Chrisman
University of Washington


Outline of Presentation


Measurement Theory

abbreviated intellectual history

Classical school

developed in physics (and related sciences) by late 19th century
numerical relationship between standard& object measured; inherent in object
Example: Legal Weights and Measures in the State of Indiana
[still a tacit part of geographic databases?]

Representationalism

Bertand Russell; Campbell; Bridgeman; Stevens ...
properties not inherent in object; numbers derive from measurement operations
20th century dominated by representationalists.


Stevens in Historical Context

Measurement theorists concentrated on physics
'extensive' measures (eg. length) emphasized strict limits; special role for addition
'Operationism' enshrines the procedure;
result: no room for social sciences

Stevens: a psychophysicist
research on perceived loudness of sound
measurements rejected by operationists
General movement for quantitative approach to social sciences


Stevens' Scales of Measurement

Published 1946 in Science (without any references)
Adopts 'nominalist' form of representationalism:
Defines measurement as 'assignment of numbers to objects according to a rule'
Measurement scale defined by properties of numbers (not properties of the rules or objects)
Scales organized by transformations under which the meaning remains invariant.
1946: Nominal, Ordinal, Interval, Ratio
(log-interval added in 1959)
Links scales to permissible statistics


Stevens' Scales of Measurement

(from Table 1, Stevens 1946, page 678)

Scale    Empirical   Invariance            Permissible
         Operations  Group                 Statistics

NOMINAL  equality    any 1:1 substitution  Mode
                                           Number of cases
										  
ORDINAL  < , >       any monotonic         Median
                     function              Percentiles
					
INTERVAL equality of x' = ax + b           Mean, std. dev.
         intervals                         Correlations
RATIO    equality of x' = ax               Coefficient of 
         ratios                            variation

Nominal Measures: Based on sets

Venn diagram of set membership Objects classified by shared attributes.
All members belong equally.
NOTE: Examples based on a footrace. "Objects" in this case are people.

[Critique of traditional categories]


Ordinal Measures

Order of arrival of contestants in footrace

         Women's race  Men's race
First    Jane          Tom
Second   Melissa       Dick
Third    Leila         Harry
...

Ordinal measures may be complete orderings, partial orderings or ranked categories
(High, Medium, Low)
(slight, medium, severe, very severe limitations)
Examples: Grading Sweet Potato crops in Indiana | Plant Hardiness in Texas


Interval Measures

Clock time of arrival at Finish Line of race Interval measures require a fixed distance, but the zero point is arbitrary.
Differences between two interval measures are ratio.
Interval measures are often raw results, with some additional relationships they become ratio.


Temperature Scales

a misleading example of interval measurement

A frequent example of interval measurement is temperature in degrees F, or °C.
The 'interval' equation does apply:
degrees F = ( 5/9 · degrees C ) + 32
BUT degrees K is not the 'true' ratio scale (extensive).

To combine regular extensive measures: ADD
To combine temperatures:
Two objects brought in contact reach a weighted equilibrium temperature.

Current Local Temperature: (Use BACK to return)


Ratio Measures

Elapsed time of race Ratio measures have:
a fixed zero that means 'no quantity';
a constant interval (distance on the scale).

May be rescaled because '1' is arbitrary.

Examples of ratio scales: Physics | Bushels in Indiana


Extensive and Derived Scales

Stevens conflated two types of ratio measures.

Extensive: based on addition rule for combination
examples: distance, mass, time
Derived: created by division of extensive measures;
velocity = distance / time , etc.

Different axioms apply
(recognized in thematic cartography practice)
Examples of Proportional Symbols and Choropleth Extensive: proportional symbols
Derived: choropleth


Stevens adds a Scale

In 1959, Stevens recognizes that the invariance rules could allow another scale on the same 'level' as interval.

The invariance function would have the form: x' = a times x to the b power

This 'log-interval' scale is mostly theoretical, though earthquake intensities on Richter and Mercali scales use this form.

None of the social science statistics textbooks take notice; cartographers still use the basic 4.


Beyond Ratio

Ratio is not the 'highest' level of measurement, '1' need not be arbitrary.

Using Stevens' invariance scheme, an 'absolute' scale could not be rescaled by any multipier.
Both zero AND one are fixed.

Probability is an absolute scale.
Bayes' Law and other axioms depend on absolute scaling.
Just as a difference of intervals is ratio, some divisions of ratios produce absolute measures.


Counts: a misfit

Some measures are obtained by tabulating the total of some objects inside a larger collecting unit.

 

Are counts higher than ratio?
Are counts 'discrete' like categorical measures?
One answer: Counts are counts;
Extend the system to handle all the cases.

 

Bizarre count data - Live!

Geiger counter in Texas |


Cyclical measures

Stevens scales only accomodate open-ended linear scales.
Some measures are cyclical, with a fixed range.
Example: Angles

Additional axioms are required to handle the fact that 359° is the same distance from 0° as 1° is.


Multidimensional measures

Multidimensional scales have extra relationships.

In Stevens' scheme, an unbounded linear axis could not be fit into a fixed interval without losing information.

yet, two unbounded Cartesian axes can be transformed into radial coordinates with only one unbounded axis, and one angle.

Conversion from Cartesian coordiantes to Radial

Multidimensional Meaurements

Physics Devices at Cornell |


Reconsidering Categories

'Nominal' measures depend upon Aristotle's view:
categories imply shared values of attributes.
Hence, test for equivalence only.

Two alternative approaches to categories:

Both provide a metric for membership beyond the simple Yes/No of traditional categories.

 

Examples

Spectral Mixtures (UW Geology) | Cluster Analysis ...


Verdict on Stevens

The four levels are not adequate.

New Requirements:

Measurement involves more axioms than just those involved in the number line.


A larger framework for measurement

Stevens never questions the nature of the 'object'.
[in psychology, the 'case' is not a problem]

Standard model: case 'has' attributes
(not relationships that can be measured)
Geographical Matrix: places 'have' attributes
'Case' permits measurement as a form of control.

Geographic control is not completely routine and accepted.
Scheme based on Sinton: fixed, controlled, measured


Measurement Frameworks


based on relationships between geometry & attribute
[Lecture on Measurement Frameworks]

Object Control
	Isolated objects: 'features'; isolines
	Connected objects: network;  coverage	
Spatial Control
	Point-based: center point
	Area-based: (many rules)
Relationship Control
	Triangular Irregular Network (TIN)
Composite Frameworks (eg. Choropleth)

Object Frameworks (Vector)

basic rules: attribute serves as control, positions measured to suit


Index from Here: | Back to Lecture | National Institute of Standards and Technology | Indiana Code on Weights and Measures |
Version of 2 October 1995